Banner Portal
Process, consciousness, and integrated information
PDF (English)

Palavras-chave

Consciousness
Integrated information theory
Interference
Process philosophy
Self-transformative process
Self-transformativeness

Como Citar

MUNETA, Enrique Aramendia. Process, consciousness, and integrated information. Manuscrito: Revista Internacional de Filosofia, Campinas, SP, v. 47, n. 1, p. e2023–0050, 2024. Disponível em: https://periodicos.sbu.unicamp.br/ojs/index.php/manuscrito/article/view/8675980. Acesso em: 10 dez. 2024.

Resumo

Process aspects are prevalent in many domains of reality, and consciousness is no exception. Nevertheless, while the processual approach implicitly underlies the theories of consciousness, an explicit statement of the question is scarcely found in the literature. This paper tries to bridge this gap. Here, I argue that conscious experience fulfils all the requirements for a processual analysis: it is complex, functionally/causally determined, and has a temporal basis. Then, I revisit an old concept, self-transformative processes, which refers to processes that change themselves. These processes are very common. A stretched bow is the classical Heraclitean example. However, it is easy to misunderstand what self-transformativeness is. To provide a well-formed description, I characterize self-transformative processes in terms of composition (using a non-classic mereology) and in terms of functionality (by developing the concept of self-modulating variables). Finally, I apply self-transformative processes to explain consciousness. Traces of self-transformativeness can be found in many theories of consciousness, particularly when they are stressed about their internal mechanisms. Here, I focus on Integrated Information Theory as a paradigmatic example of a mathematically well-described theory, and I demonstrate that quantitative self-transformativeness is a requirement at the very core of the integration of the information.

PDF (English)

Referências

Alpern, M. (1953). “Metacontrast.” Journal of the Optical Society of America, 43(8), 648-657.

Aramendia, E. (2022). Conciencia, proceso y autotransformatividad (Tesis). Universidad Complutense de Madrid, Madrid.

Baars, B. J. (1988). A cognitive theory of consciousness. Cambridge University Press.

Bachmann, T. (2000). Microgenetic approach to the conscious mind (Vol. 25). Amsterdam/Philadephia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

Bachmann, T., & Francis, G. (2014). Visual Masking: Studing Perception, Attention and Consciousness. Oxford: Academic Press. Elvesier.

Balduzzi, D., & Tononi, G. (2008). “Integrated Information in Discrete Dynamical Systems: Motivation and Theoretical Framework.” PLoS Computational Biology, 4(6): e1000091. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1000091

Bayne, T. (2018). “On the axiomatic foundations of the integrated information theory of consciousness.” Neuroscience of Consciousness, 2018. https://doi.org/10.1093/nc/niy007

Bayne, T., & Chalmers, D. J. [David J.] (2003). “What is the unity of consciousness?” In A. Cleeremans (Ed.), The unity of consciousness: Binding, integration, and dissociation (pp. 23-58). Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198508571.003.0002

Bickhard, M. H. (2003). “Process and Emergence: Normative Function and Representation.” In J. Seibt (Ed.), Process Theories: Crossdisciplinary Studies in Dynamic Categories (pp. 121-155). Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1044-3_6

Blake, R., & Logothetis, N. K. (2002). “Visual competition.” Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 3(1), 13-21.

Block, N. J. (1995). “On a Confusion About a Function of Consciousness.” Brain and Behavioral Sciences, 18(2), 227-247.

Block, N. J. (2011). “Perceptual consciousness overflows cognitive access.” Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(12), 567-575. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2011.11.001

Block, N. J., & Fodor, J. A. (1972). What psychological states are not. The Philosophical Review, 159-181.

Brentano, F. (1874). Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkte. Leipzig: Duncker & Humblot.

Brunton, S. L., & Kutz, J. N. (2019). Data-Driven Science and Engineering: Machine Learning, Dynamical Systems, and Control. Cambridge University Press.

Chalmers, D. J. [David John] (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory (1. issued as an Oxford University Press paperback). Oxford paperbacks. New York: Oxford Univ. Press.

Cleeremans, A. (Ed.) (2003). The unity of consciousness: Binding, integration, and dissociation (Reprinted.). Oxford: Oxford University Press . https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198508571.001.0001

Cohen, M. A., & Dennett, D. C. [Daniel C.] (2011). “Consciousness cannot be separated from function.” Trends in Cognitive Sciences , 15(8), 358-364. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tics.2011.06.008

Cotnoir, A., & Bacon, A. (2012). “Non-Wellfounded Mereology.” The Review of Symbolic Logic, 5, 187-204. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1755020311000293

Crane, T. (2000). “The Origins of Qualia.” In T. Crane & S. Patterson (Eds.), London studies in the history of philosophy: Vol. 3. History of the mind-body problem (pp. 169-194). London, New York: Routledge.

Crane, T., & Patterson, S. (Eds.) (2000). London studies in the history of philosophy: Vol. 3. History of the mind-body problem. London, New York: Routledge .

Dainton, B. (2000). Stream of consciousness: Unity and continuity in conscious experience (Rev. pbk. ed.). International library of philosophy. London, New York: Routledge .

Dainton, B. (2018). “Temporal Consciousness.” In Zalta, Edward N. (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2018th ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

Dehaene, S. (2014). Consciousness and the brain: Deciphering how the brain codes our thoughts. New York New York: Viking.

Dehaene, S., Changeux, J.-P., & Naccache, L. (2011). “The global neuronal workspace model of conscious access: from neuronal architectures to clinical applications.” In S. Dehaene & Y. Christen (Eds.), Characterizing Consciousness: From Cognition to the Clinic? (pp. 55-84). Springer.

Dehaene, S., & Christen, Y. (Eds.) (2011). Characterizing Consciousness: From Cognition to the Clinic? Springer.

Dehaene, S., & Naccache, L. (2001). “Towards a cognitive neuroscience of consciousness: basic evidence and a workspace framework.” Cognition, 79(1), 1-37. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0010-0277(00)00123-2

Dehaene, S., Naccache, L., Cohen, L., Bihan, D. L., Mangin, J. F., Poline, J. B., & Rivière, D. (2001). “Cerebral mechanisms of word masking and unconscious repetition priming.” Nature Neuroscience, 4(7), 752-758.

Del Cul, A., Baillet, S., & Dehaene, S. (2007). “Brain Dynamics Underlying the Nonlinear Threshold for Access to Consciousness.” PLoS Biology, 5(10): e260. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pbio.0050260

Dretske, F. I. (1995). Naturalizing the mind. The Jean Nicod lectures: Vol. 1994. Cambridge Mass.: MIT press.

Eastman, T., & Keeton, H. (Eds.) (2004). Physics & Whitehead: Quantum, Process and Experience. Albany: State University of New York Press.

Eccles, John C. (ed.) (1966): Brain and conscious experience. Berlin, Heidelberg, New York: Springer-Verlag.

Edelman, G. M. (1989). The remembered present: A biological theory of consciousness. New York: Basic Books.

Farrell, J., & McClelland, T. (2017). “Editorial: Consciousness and Inner Awareness.” Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 8(1), 1-22. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-017-0331-x

Forman, R. K. C. (1990). “Introduction: Mysticism, Constructivism, and Forgetting.” In R. K. C. Forman (Ed.), The Problem of Pure Consciousness: Mysticism and Philosophy (pp. 3-49). New York: Oxford University Press.

Forman, R. K. C. (Ed.) (1990). The Problem of Pure Consciousness: Mysticism and Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press .

Guillot, M. (2017). “I Me Mine: On a Confusion Concerning the Subjective Character of Experience.” Review of Philosophy and Psychology , 8(1), 23-53. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-016-0313-4

Hameroff, S., & Penrose, R. (1996). “Orchestrated reduction of quantum coherence in brain microtubules: A model for consciousness.” Mathematics and Computers in Simulation, 40(3-4), 453-480. https://doi.org/10.1016/0378-4754(96)80476-9

Hansen, N. V. (2004). “Spacetime and becoming: Overcoming the contradiction between special relativity and the passage of time.” In T. Eastman & H. Keeton (Eds.), Physics & Whitehead: Quantum, Process and Experience (pp. 136-163). Albany: State University of New York Press .

Husserl, E. (1913). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung: Erster buch. Halle: Max Niemeyer.

Jackendoff, R. (1994). Consciousness and the computational mind (4. print). A Bradford book: Vol. 3. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT press.

Jackson, F. (1982). “Epiphenomenal Qualia.” The Philosophical Quarterly (1950-), 32(127), 127-136. https://doi.org/10.2307/2960077

James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology, Vol I. Ed. 1931 New York: Henry Holt and Co.

Koch, C. (2004). The Quest for Consciousness. Roberts and Company.

Kooi, B. (1981). “On the mechanics of the bow and arrow.” Journal of Engineering Mathematics 15, 119-145.

Kriegel, U. (2009). Subjective consciousness: A self-representational theory. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press .

Krishnaswamy, P., & Nair, S. (2016). “Effect of Music Therapy on Pain and Anxiety Levels of Cancer Patients: A Pilot Study.” Indian Journal of Palliative Care, 22(3), 307-311. https://doi.org/10.4103/0973-1075.185042

Lamme, V. A. F. (2010). “How neuroscience will change our view on consciousness.” Cognitive Neuroscience, 1(3), 204-220. https://doi.org/10.1080/17588921003731586

Leopold, D. A., & Logothetis, N. K. (1996). “Activity changes in early visual cortex reflect monkeys' percepts during binocular rivalry.” Nature, 379(6565)(Feb 8), 549-553.

Libet, Benjamin (1966): Brain stimulation and the threshold of conscious experience. En: John C. Eccles (ed.): Brain and conscious experience. Berlin, Heidelberg, New York: Springer-Verlag , pág. 165-181.

Libet, Benjamin; Wright, E. W., JR; Feinstein, B.; Pearl, D. K. (1979): Subjective referral of the timing for a conscious sensory experience: a functional role for the somatosensory specific projection system in man. En: Brain 102 (1), pág. 193-224. DOI: 10.1093/brain/102.1.193.

Locke, J. (1689). An essay concerning human understanding Twenty-fifth edition, 1825. London: Thomas Davidson, Whitefriars.

Logothetis, N. K., & Schall, J. D. (1989). “Neuronal correlates of subjective visual perception.” Science, 245(4919), 761-763.

Mangan, B. (1993). “Taking Phenomenology Seriously: The "Fringe" and Its Implications for Cognitive Research.” Consciousness and Cognition, 2(2), 89-108. https://doi.org/10.1006/ccog.1993.1008

Metzinger, T. (Ed.) (2015). Open MIND. Mainz: Frankfurt am Main : MIND Group.

Montemayor, C. (2017). “Conscious awareness and time perception.” PsyCh Journal, 6(3), 228-238. https://doi.org/10.1002/pchj.173

Nagel, T. (1974). “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” The Philosophical Review , 83(4), 435-450. https://doi.org/10.2307/2183914

Nicholson, D. J., & Dupré, J. (Eds.) (2018). Everything flows: Towards a processual philosophy of biology (First edition, Vol. 1). Oxford United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198779636.001.0001

O’Shaughnessy, B. (2000). Consciousness and the World. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.

Oizumi, M., Albantakis, L., & Tononi, G. (2014). “From the phenomenology to the mechanisms of consciousness: Integrated Information Theory 3.0.” PLoS Computational Biology , May 8, 2014. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pcbi.1003588

Rashbrook, O. (2013). “Diachronic and synchronic unity.” Philosophical Studies, 164(2), 465-484. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-012-9865-z

Rescher, N. (1996). Process metaphysics: An introduction to process philosophy. Suny Press.

Rescher, N. (1998). Complexity: A philosophical overview. Transaction Publishers.

Rescher, N. (2000). Process philosophy: A survey of basic issues. University of Pittsburgh Pre.

Revonsuo, A. (1999). “Binding and the phenomenal unity of consciousness.” Consciousness and Cognition , 8(2), 173-185. https://doi.org/10.1006/ccog.1999.0384

Rosenthal, D. M. (2005). Consciousness and mind. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press .

Searle, J. R. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge University Press.

Searle, J. R. (1992). The rediscovery of the mind. Representation and mind. Cambridge, London: MIT press.

Searle, J. R., Dennett, D. C. [D. C.], & Chalmers, D. J. [David John] (1997). The mystery of consciousness (1st ed.). New York: New York Review of Books.

Sebastián, M. Á. (2012). “Experiential Awareness: Do You Prefer “It” to “Me”?” Philosophical Topics, 40(2), 155-177.

Seibt, J. (Ed.) (2003). Process Theories: Crossdisciplinary Studies in Dynamic Categories. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands . https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1044-3

Seibt, J. (2009). “Forms of emergent interaction in General Process Theory.” Synthese, 166(3), 479. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-008-9373-z

Seibt, J. (2015). “Non-Transitive Parthood, Leveled Mereology, and the Representation of Emergent Parts of Processes.” Grazer Philosophische Studien, 91(1), 165-190. https://doi.org/10.1163/9789004302273_008

Seibt, J. (2018). “Ontological Tools for the Process Turn in Biology: Some Basic Notions of General Process Theory.” In D. J. Nicholson & J. Dupré (Eds.), Everything flows: Towards a processual philosophy of biology (Vol. 1, pp. 113-136). Oxford United Kingdom: Oxford University Press . https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198779636.003.0006

Seibt, J. (2020). Process Philosophy. In Zalta, Edward N. (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2020th ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

Seibt, J., Imaguire, G., & Gerogiorgakis, S. (2017). Handbook of Mereology. München: Philosophia Verlag München.

Seth, A. K. (2014): A predictive processing theory of sensorimotor contingencies: Explaining the puzzle of perceptual presence and its absence in synesthesia. En: Cognitive neuroscience 5 (2), pág. 97-118.

Seth, A. K. (2021): Being you. A new science of consciousness. London: Faber & Faber.

Shapiro, L. (2011). Embodied cognition. New problems of philosophy. New York, NY, US: Routledge/Taylor & Francis Group.

Simons, P. M. (1987). Parts: A study in ontology. New York: Oxford University Press .

Sperling, G. (1960). “The information available in brief visual presentations.” Psychological Monographs: General and Applied, 74(11), 1-29. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0093759

Strogatz, S. H. (1994). Nonlinear dynamics and chaos: With applications to Physics, Biology, Chemics and Engineering. Readings, Massachusetts: Perseus Books.

Thompson, E. (2015). “Dreamless Sleep, the Embodied Mind, and Consciousness: The Relevance of a Classical Indian Debate to Cognitive Science.” In T. Metzinger (Ed.), Open MIND (37(T), pp. 1-19). Mainz: Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. https://doi.org/10.31231/osf.io/d9gqa

Tononi, G. (2008). “Consciousness as integrated information: a provisional manifesto.” The Biological Bulletin, 215(3), 216-242.

Tononi, G., & Koch, C. (2015). “Consciousness: Here, There and Everywhere?” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences, 370. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2014.0167

Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness: A representational theory of the phenomenal mind. Representation and mind. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT press .

Tye, M. (2003). Consciousness and persons: Unity and identity. A Bradford book. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT press .

Vandenbroucke, A. R. E., Sligte, I. G., Barrett, A. B., Seth, A. K., Fahrenfort, J. J., & Lamme, V. A. F. (2014). “Accurate Metacognition for Visual Sensory Memory Representations” Psychological Science, 25(4), 861-873.

Varela, F., Lachaux, J.-P., Rodriguez, E., & Martinerie, J. (2001). “The brainweb: Phase synchronization and large-scale integration.” Nature Reviews. Neuroscience, 2(4), 229-239. https://doi.org/10.1038/35067550

Varzi, A. (2019). “Mereology.” In Zalta, Edward N. (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2019th ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

Watanabe, E., Matsunaga, W., & Kitaoka, A. (2010). “Motion signals deflect relative positions of moving objects.” Vision Research, 50(23), 2381-2390. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.visres.2010.09.021

Wiener, N. (1948). Cybernetics; or control and communication in the animal and the machine. John Wiley.

Windt, J. M. (2015). “Just in Time-Dreamless Sleep Experience as Pure Subjective Temporality: A Commentary on Evan Thompson.” In T. Metzinger (Ed.), Open MIND (37(C), pp. 1-34). Mainz: Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group. https://doi.org/10.15502/9783958571174

Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophische Untersuchungen. Oxford: Blackwell.

Zahavi, D. (2005). Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. Cambridge Mass.: MIT press .

Zalta, Edward N. (Ed.) (2018). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

Zalta, Edward N. (Ed.) (2019). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

Zalta, Edward N. (Ed.) (2020). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2020). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.

Zaniewski, I. (2009). “Modeling of the Archery Bow and Arrow Vibrations.” Shock and Vibration 16 (3), 307-317.

Creative Commons License

Este trabalho está licenciado sob uma licença Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License.

Copyright (c) 2024 Manuscrito: Revista Internacional de Filosofia

Downloads

Não há dados estatísticos.