Banner Portal
Kant and the construction of pure reason
PDF

Keywords

Constructivism
Chemical experiment
Kant
Pure reason

How to Cite

KLEIN, Joel Thiago. Kant and the construction of pure reason: an analogy with a chemical experiment. Manuscrito: International Journal of Philosophy, Campinas, SP, v. 46, n. 1, p. 29–76, 2023. Disponível em: https://periodicos.sbu.unicamp.br/ojs/index.php/manuscrito/article/view/8674097. Acesso em: 21 may. 2024.

Abstract

This paper defends a constructive interpretation of the Critique of Pure Reason, which is built in analogy with an experimental construction that Kant believes to characteristic of chemistry. I also argue for a way to reconcile the methodological perspective of the constructivist method with that of transcendental reflection. I therefore provide a constructive explanation for what Kant describes as being pure reason and the argument of the transcendental deduction. I propose to frame the different perspectives in such a way that the experimental construction is the ratio cognoscendi of pure reason, while pure reason is the ratio essendi of the experimental construction. O’Neill (19892015) is one of the most important scholars that have argued for a constructivist reading of the Critique of pure reason (CPR). In this paper I develop and explore new aspects of this line of interpretation. One of the main criticisms raised against constructivist readings of Kant’s philosophy is an alleged commitment to subjectivism or voluntarism (cf. Kleingeld & Willaschek 2019). This concern led some scholars to rename their position as constitutivist instead (Korsgaard 2009Sensen 20132017Formosa 2011). Constitutivism, is intended to be a sort of constructivism capable of avoiding voluntarism. However, it becomes difficult, sometimes, to differentiate between the constitutivist and foundationalist positions, which are based on transcendental reflection and imply a sort of realist perspective on reason. The same preoccupation applies to the constructivist interpretation of the CPR. In order to deal with this issue, the following questions must be addressed: how can constructivism justify the necessity and universality of transcendental principles of pure reason without compromising the normative and procedural aspects of the construction? How to reconcile arguments based on the analysis of representations and faculties with a constructivist procedure? Or even, how may transcendental reflection, as a view of the possibility of a priori cognition, be rendered compatible with a constructive procedure? This paper is divided into three sections, followed by brief final remarks. The first section outlines the main characteristics of constructivism and relates them to Kant’s positions about the nature of philosophy and its method. The second part argues for a type of experimental constructivism that might serve as a guiding analogy to understand the method underlying the CPR. Thirdly, I will show how the transcendental subject and pure reason are derived from this experimental construction. The conclusion briefly points out some advantages of this position.

PDF

References

Bacon, Francis (2000): The New Organon. Cambridge texts in the history of philosophy. Cambridge.

Formosa, Paul (2011): Is Kant a Moral Constructivist or a Moral Realist?, in: European Journal of Philosophy 19(3), pp.1-27.

Förster, Eckart (ed.) (1989): Kant’s Transcendental Deductions, Stanford.

Gloy, Karen (1996): Kants Philosophie und das Experiment, in: Schönrich, Gerhard; and Kato, Yasushi (Hrsg.) Kant in der Diskussion der Moderne, Frakfurt am Main.

Henrich, Dieter (1966): Zu Kants Begriff der Philosophie, In: Kaulbach, Friedrich; ritter, Joachim (Eds.). Kritik und Metaphysik (Festschrift für Heinz Heimsoeth), Berlin, pp. 40-59.

_____. (1969): The Proof-Structure of Kant's Transcendental Deduction, in: The Review of Metaphysics, 22(4), pp. 640-659.

_____. (1975): Die Deduktion des Sittengesetztes, in: Schwan, A (Org.). Denken im Schatten des Nihilismus. Festschrift für Wilhelm Weischedel zum 70. Geburststag. Darmstadt.

_____. (1984): Die Beweisstruktur der transzendentalen Deduktion der reinen Verstandesbegriffe, in: Tuschling, B. (Org.). Probleme der 'Kritik der reinen Vernunft'. Kant-Tagung Marburg 1981, Berlin.

_____. (1989): Kant’s Notion of a deduction and the Methodological Background of the First Critique, in: Förster, Eckart (ed.). Kant's Transcendental Deductions. Stanford.

_____. (2001): Systemform und Abschlussgedanke. Methode und Metaphysik als Problem in Kants Denken, in: Gerhardt, V. (Orgs.). Kant und die Berliner Aufklärung, Berlin.

Höffe, Otfried (2003): Kants Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Die Grundlegung der Moderne Philosophie. München.

Kaulbach, Friedrich (1978): Das Prinzip Handlung in der Philosophie Kants. Berlin.

Klein, T. Joel (2020): Systematic perspectives on the distinction between appearances and things in themselves in the Critique of Pure Reason, in: Studia Kantiana, v. 18, p. 139-175.

_____. (2019): Ciência e Método em Bacon e Kant, in: Revista Dissertatio de Filosofia, v. 49, p. 287-311.

Kleingeld, Pauline & Willascheck, Marcus (2019): Autonomy without Paradox: Kant, Self-Legislation and the Moral Law, in: Philosophers’s Imprint v.19, n.6, pp.1-18.

Korsgaard, Christine M. (1996): Creating the Kingdom of Ends, Cambridge.

_____. (1996b): The Sources of Normativity, Cambridge.

_____. (2009): Self-Constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity, Oxford.

Møller, S. (2020). Kant's Tribunal of Reason: Legal Metaphor and Normativity in the Critique of Pure Reason. Cambridge University Press.

O’Neill, Onora, (1989): Constructions of Reason, Cambridge University Press.

_____. (2015): Constructing Authorities, Cambridge University Press.

Pievatolo, Maria Chiara (1999): The Tribunal of Reason: Kant and the Juridical Nature of Pure Reason, in: Ratio Juris, 12, pp. 311-327.

Proops, Ian (2003): Kant's Legal Metaphor and the Nature of a Deduction, in: Journal of the History of Philosophy, 41 (2), pp. 209-229.

Rawls, John (1980): Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory, in: Journal of Philosophy 77, pp. 515-72. Reprinted in Rawls 1999b, pp.303-58.

Rawls, John (1989): Themes in Kant’s Moral Philosophy, in: Förster (ed.): 81-113. Reprinted in Rawls 1999, pp. 497-528.

_____. (1996): Political Liberalism, rev. ed., New York.

_____. (1999a): A Theory of Justice, rev. 2nd., Oxford.

_____. (1999b): Collected Papers, ed. S. Freeman, Cambridge, MA: Harvard.

Reath, Andrews (2006): Agency and Autonomy in Kant’s Moral Theory: Selected Essays. Oxford.

Schafer, Karl (2019): Kant: Constitutivism as capacities-first philosophy, in. Philosophical explorations. DOI: 10.1080/13869795.2019.1599049

Seeberg, Ulrich (2007): Kants Vernunftkritik als Gerichtsprozeß. In: Bowman, B. (Org.). Darstellung und Erkenntnis. Paderborn.

Sensen, Oliver (2013): Kant's Constructisivm, in: Bagnoli, Carla (ed.): Constructivism in Ethics, Cambridge University Press, pp. 63-81.

_____. (2017): Kant's Constitutivism, in: E. Schmidt and R. dos Santos (eds.), Realism and Antirealism in Kant's Moral Philosophy (New Essays), Berlin, pp. 197-220.

_____. (2013): Moral Skepticism, Constructivism, and the Value of Humanity, in: Carla Bagnoli (ed.), Constructivism in Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 22-41.

Trevisan, Diego K. (2018): Der Gerichtshof der Vernunft: Eine historische und systematische Untersuchung über die juridischen Metaphern der Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Würzburg.

Wind, Edgar (2001): Das experiment und die Metaphysik, Frakfurt am Main.

Creative Commons License

This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License.

Copyright (c) 2023 Manuscrito: International Journal of Philosophy

Downloads

Download data is not yet available.